Headnotes to the Judgment of the Second Senate of 18 December 1984
- 2 BvE 13/83 -
1. a) Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law must be interpreted in light of Art. 20(2) of the Basic Law. An extension of the powers of participation granted to the Bundestag by Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law with regard to the formation of the political will of the state on foreign affairs that goes beyond the acts of international law defined therein would encroach on the central decision-making powers of the executive and run counter to the system of distribution of power, responsibility and oversight provided for in the Basic Law.
b) It cannot be inferred from Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law that every action of the Federal Government under international law that governs the political relations of the Federal Republic of Germany or concerns matters of federal legislation must be in the form of an international treaty that requires the consent or participation of the legislator.
2. a) Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law does not require that the transfer of German sovereign powers to international organisations must be irrevocable.
b) It cannot be inferred from Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law that an act only amounts to a transfer of sovereign powers when an international organisation is granted the power to take measures with direct legal consequences for individuals.
c) Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law does not prevent the provision of territory by the Federal Republic of Germany for the stationing of allied forces in the context of a defensive alliance or the approval of decision-making structures for the deployment of these forces that serve the defensive purpose of the alliance in order to ensure the protection of the Federal Republic of Germany against attacks and thus also protect the integrity of its constitutional order and its sovereignty.
3. The Federal Government is charged with carrying out assessments and evaluations concerning foreign and defence policy. The Basic Law limits this power only in the case of manifest arbitrariness. If this absolute limit is not crossed, it is not for the Federal Constitutional Court to review whether the Federal Government’s assessments or evaluations are correct, as no legal standards exist in this respect; rather, the Federal Government must assume political responsibility for these assessments and evaluations.
4. Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law and Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law are exhaustive with regard to the matters covered therein; legislative powers of the Bundestag thus do not arise independently from the principle of democracy or the significance and implications that a decision might have for the state as a whole. Under the democratic and parliamentary order of the Basic Law, the government also has democratic legitimation in terms of its institution, functions and members and is not from the outset limited to carrying out acts of lesser political significance.
FEDERAL CONSTITUTIONAL COURT
- 2 BvE 13/83 -
IN THE NAME OF THE PEOPLE
In the proceedings
on
the application to declare that
the Federal Government, by consenting to the forces of the United States of America stationed in Germany being provided with Pershing-2 missiles with nuclear warheads and cruise missiles without obtaining the constitutionally required Bundestag authorisation through an act of Parliament, violated the rights of the Bundestag under Art. 79(1) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 24(1), Art. 25, and Art. 59(2) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 20(3) of the Basic Law
Applicant: Parliamentary group in the German Bundestag DIE GRÜNEN,
represented by its spokespersons Marieluise Beck-Oberdorf, Petra Kelly, Otto Schily, Bundeshaus, Bonn l
- authorised representative: … -,
Respondent: Federal Government,
represented by the Federal Chancellor, Federal Chancellery, Bonn I -
- authorised representative: … -,
the Federal Constitutional Court – Second Senate –
with the participation of Justices
President Zeidler,
Rinck,
Niebler,
Steinberger,
Träger,
Mahrenholz,
Böckenförde,
Klein
held on the basis of the oral hearing of 17 July 1984:
Judgment:
The application is rejected.
Reasons:
A.-I.
1
The proceedings concern the question of whether the Federal Government, by consenting to the deployment of US medium-range ballistic missiles with nuclear warheads of the type Pershing-2 and cruise missiles in the Federal Republic of Germany without a specific statutory basis, violated rights of the Bundestag or directly threatened to violate such rights. […]
II.
2
1. The applicant is the parliamentary group in the Bundestag for DIE GRÜNEN.
3
a) With its submission instituting the Organstreit proceedings (dispute between constitutional organs), which the Federal Constitutional Court received on 16 November 1983, the parliamentary group lodged an application to declare as follows:
4
The Federal Government, by consenting to the armed forces of the United States of America stationed in Germany being provided with Pershing-2 ballistic missiles with nuclear warheads and cruise missiles without obtaining the constitutionally required Bundestag authorisation through an act of Parliament, violated the rights of the Bundestag under Art. 79(1) first sentence and Art. 20(3) in conjunction with Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law.
5
In the oral hearing of 17 July 1984, the applicant amended the application […].
6-12
b) […]
13
2. The respondent in the present proceedings is the Federal Government.
14
a) The Federal Government considers the application to be inadmissible.
15-18
[…]
19
b) The Federal Government also considers the application to be unfounded.
20-26
[…]
27-32
3. […]
33
In order to clarify that the assertion of a violation of rights of the Bundestag under Art. 79(1) first sentence of the Basic Law (Grundgesetz – GG) was based on Art. 24(1) and Art. 25 of the Basic Law, and to illustrate the relationship between Art. 20(3) and Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law as set forth in the aforementioned submissions, the applicant amended its application in the oral hearing as follows:
34
The Federal Government, by consenting to the armed forces of the United States of America stationed in Germany being provided with Pershing-2 ballistic missiles with nuclear warheads and cruise missiles without obtaining the constitutionally required Bundestag authorisation through an act of Parliament, violated the rights of the Bundestag under Art. 79(1) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 24(1) and Art. 25 and under Art. 59(2) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 20(3) of the Basic Law.
35-40
[…]
41
4. In the oral hearing at the Federal Constitutional Court and in a subsequently filed submission, the applicant reaffirmed its views and added to its previous submissions.
42-44
a) […]
45
The applicant requested that experts be heard to take evidence on the following assertions:
46
1) The Pershing II is a ballistic missile that can reach the western Soviet Union as far as Moscow in about 12-14 minutes after launch from the Federal Republic of Germany. It is thus far superior to even the fastest fighter jets.
2) Owing to its active guidance system for the final flight phase, the Pershing II has the highest accuracy of all missile systems currently available to the US (including intercontinental ballistic missiles). The (intercontinental) MX, which will be operational in 1986, and the Trident II submarine-launched missile, which will be operational in 1989, will be capable of targeting and destroying fortified targets in the Soviet Union (especially command, communications and control centres).
3) The Pershing II has a penetration capability against which the Soviet Union has no means of defence. By contrast, the Soviet Union has a high defence capability against fighter jets.
4) In contrast to both the conventional fighter aircraft and cruise missiles (unmanned aircraft, no ballistic carriers) currently deployed in the UK and Italy, which are kept in armoured hangars, the Pershing II missiles are deployed without protection; they therefore have little chance of survival in the case of a possible attack. In the event that they are under threat, or merely suspected of being under threat, they must either be withdrawn from Germany or fired early.
5) The short warning times brought about by the deployment of medium-range missiles in Central Europe have contributed to the trend towards automating information and decision-making processes with regard to the use of these missiles.
6) The technical capabilities of the Pershing II mean that it is a military warfare tool capable of directly destroying operational targets in the Soviet Union from the territory of the Federal Republic of Germany in a targeted, selective manner and on a purely military mission. It allows a shift in military strategy from deterrence through mutual assured destruction to warfare deterrence, i.e. a shift from the threat of nuclear annihilation to the threat of defeat in a nuclear war.
7) The deployment of 108 Pershing II systems on the territory of the Federal Republic of Germany expands US military strategic choices vis-à-vis the Soviet Union. In particular, the United States gains the possibility of pursuing military objectives outside the purposes of the NATO alliance.
47
[…]
48
b) The Federal Government countered the applicant’s statements in the oral hearing.
49-74
1. [...]
75
The Federal Government opposes the applicant’s request for taking evidence on the grounds that there is no need to do so because the assertions are irrelevant to the pending proceedings.
B.-I.
76
The application is admissible.
77
1. As a parliamentary group in the 10th German Bundestag, the applicant has the legal ability to be a party to the proceedings pursuant to §§ 13 no. 5 and 63 ff. of the Federal Constitutional Court Act (Bundesverfassungsgerichtsgesetz – BVerfGG) (Decisions of the Federal Constitutional Court, Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts – BVerfGE 2, 143 <160>; established case-law). According to § 63 of the Federal Constitutional Court Act, the Federal Government, against whom the application is directed, can be a respondent in Organstreit proceedings.
78
2. The subject matter in Organstreit proceedings is not only limited to the challenged conduct of the respondent, it is also circumscribed by the provisions of the Basic Law which the challenged acts or omissions are asserted to have violated (§ 64(2) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act). The Federal Constitutional Court must adhere to this limitation of the subject matter (BVerfGE 2, 347 <367 f.>); § 64(2) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act is a binding procedural provision (BVerfGE 2, 143 <172>). […]
79
In its submission initiating the proceedings, the applicant stated that Art. 79(1) and Art. 20(3) in conjunction with Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law have been violated, whereas in its [amended] application in the oral hearing on 17 July 1984, it stated that Art. 79(1) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 24(1), Art. 25 and Art. 59(2) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 20(3) of the Basic Law have been violated.
80
This does not amount to a change of the subject matter of the proceedings. The term ‘application’ in § 64(2) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act does not only refer to the operative part of the Court’s decision that is formally requested with the application. Rather, the provisions of the Basic Law that are claimed to have been violated by the challenged act can also be inferred from the reasons provided to substantiate the application (BVerfGE 4, 115 <123>). When the applicant’s submissions are assessed on this basis, it becomes clear that the applicant also considers that the Federal Government’s actions violate provisions of the Basic Law other than those set forth in the original application.
81-82
[…]
83
3. With regard to this subject matter, the applicant has standing to bring a challenge to the Federal Government’s actions, but not all challenges raised by the applicant are admissible.
84
a) An applicant has standing if the Court can decide a matter vis-à-vis the applicant. This is determined by substantive law (including procedural provisions and provisions on competences) and, more specifically, by the question of whether a party to the proceedings asserts its own rights, which are accorded to them by substantive law, or is authorised to assert the rights of others in their own name.
85
In its established case-law, the Federal Constitutional Court has recognised that a parliamentary group in the Bundestag may also assert rights that the Bundestag possesses vis-à-vis a respondent in its own name (BVerfGE 2, 143 <165>; established case-law). A parliamentary group may assert such rights by way of vicarious standing (Prozessstandschaft) insofar as it claims that an act or omission of the respondent violates or directly threatens to violate the Bundestag’s rights and obligations following from the Basic Law (§ 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act).
86
b) The applicant makes use of this possibility in the present proceedings. It is immaterial in this respect that the applicant does not apply for a declaration that the Basic Law has been violated, which would reflect the wording of § 67 of the Federal Constitutional Court Act, but instead applies for a declaration that the rights of the Bundestag have been violated. The application also encompasses the former declaration (cf. BVerfGE 2, 347 <366 f.>).
87
c) In this case, the challenged act within the meaning of § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act is the Federal Government’s declaration of consent regarding the deployment of the weapon systems in question.
88
aa) According to the wording of its application, the applicant claims that the Federal Government has violated rights of the Bundestag by failing to submit a bill to the Bundestag which, if adopted, would have authorised the Federal Government to consent to the armed forces of the United States stationed in Germany being equipped with Pershing-2 missiles with nuclear warheads and cruise missiles; according to the application, this failure to act was in breach of the Basic Law.
89
This submission would only be plausible if bills of this type could not be introduced from the floor of the Bundestag (Art. 76 of the Basic Law). Some legal scholars contend that the right to introduce bills on the approval of treaties within the meaning of Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law in the Bundestag is reserved for the Federal Government ([…]), while others take the view that the rules of Art. 76 of the Basic Law apply ‘without exception’ ([…]). This question need not be decided here, as the declaration of consent given by the Federal Government does not amount to a declaration to conclude a treaty within the meaning of Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law. No other legal limitations are ascertainable that would have precluded members of the Bundestag from introducing the bill sought by the applicant. In this case, a violation of the rights and obligations of the Bundestag by the Federal Government within the meaning of § 64 of the Federal Constitutional Court Act cannot be found to exist when the Federal Government merely fails to do what members of the Bundestag can do themselves. Thus, if the application were construed as a challenge regarding the mere omission to introduce a bill, it would be inadmissible and would have to be dismissed.
90
A possible breach of duty by the Federal Government through its failure to introduce such a bill in the Bundestag does not result from the special cooperative relationship between the Federal Government and the Bundestag in foreign affairs that is asserted by the applicant. It is true that the principle that a constitutional organ must take into consideration the interests of other constitutional organs when exercising its competences (cf. BVerfGE 35, 257 <261 f.>; 45, 1 <39>) may give rise to rights and obligations within the meaning of § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act, particularly review, information and consultation obligations that enable the other constitutional organs to adequately exercise their competences. However, the applicant did not submit any arguments suggesting that the Federal Government, through an omission in violation of its obligations, prevented the Bundestag from exercising its competences in foreign affairs or thwarted their exercise; nor are such circumstances otherwise ascertainable. The deployment of the US weapon systems in question on German territory was addressed by the Bundestag in detail on several occasions. […]
91
bb) Although the Federal Constitutional Court’s review is limited to the subject matter set forth in the application, the Court is not bound by the wording of the application (cf. BVerfGE 1, 14 <39>); rather, the actual nature of the procedural relief sought thereby is decisive. When the reasons given in the application are taken into account, as is required, it follows that the applicant considers the violation of rights of the Bundestag to arise from the fact that the Federal Government gave its consent to the deployment without having been authorised to do so by a specific law, which, in the applicant’s view, was necessary under constitutional law. The applicant does not seek to initiate a legislative process; rather, it wants the Court to declare that the Government’s consent to the deployment violated rights of the Bundestag within the meaning of § 64 of the Federal Constitutional Court Act on the grounds that said consent was given without sufficient statutory authorisation. In adopting this interpretation, the Federal Constitutional Court does not alter the subject matter of the proceedings – which it would be prohibited from doing (cf. BVerfGE 2, 347 <367>); it merely clarifies the meaning of the application.
92
d) With regard to the facts of the case as submitted by the applicant, it cannot be ruled out that the challenged declaration of consent could have violated or directly threatened to violate rights conferred on the Bundestag by the Basic Law (§ 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act).
93
aa) At least insofar as the applicant asserts a violation of rights of the Bundestag following from Art. 79(1) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law and from Art. 59(2) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 20(3) of the Basic Law, the applicant has vicarious standing to assert a possible violation of rights. Art. 24(1) and Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law confer legislative powers on the Bundestag in the area of foreign affairs and, in this respect, constitute rights of the Bundestag within the meaning of § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act (cf. BVerfGE 2, 347 <368, 379>). The challenged declaration of consent of the Federal Government is an act concerning foreign affairs. It cannot be ruled out from the outset that a statutory authorisation for such declaration in accordance with the affected provisions of the Basic Law was necessary, or that the Federal Government disregarded limits of existing statutory authorisations in an unconstitutional manner that violated the aforementioned legislative powers of the Bundestag.
94
bb) By contrast, insofar as the applicant claims that rights of the Bundestag within the meaning of § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act have been violated by the Federal Government’s giving of consent because it has substantive effects on fundamental rights, surrenders the core of national sovereignty that, according to the applicant, is imperative under constitutional law, or because it might violate general rules of international law within the meaning of Art. 25 of the Basic Law, its challenges are inadmissible. Neither the fundamental rights, nor the sovereignty of the Federal Republic of Germany, nor the general rules of international law give rise to rights of the Bundestag as such within the meaning of § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act. […]
95
cc) In particular, the applicant’s challenge that the consent in question violates rights of the Bundestag arising from the limitation clause in Art. 2(2) third sentence of the Basic Law is inadmissible. The applicant takes the view that the legislator failed to take into account the increased risks to the lives of fundamental rights holders protected by Art. 2(2) first sentence of the Basic Law that arise from the deployment of the new weapons. […]
96
In doing so, the applicant does not claim that, by declaring its consent, the Federal Government exceeded the limits of its statutory scope of action. Rather, with this challenge, the applicant assumes that while the Government has the ability to take such course of action, it would have needed to enact a law providing for additional prerequisites and procedural rules to exercise this ability. The applicant therefore considers the existing law to be insufficient under the essential matters doctrine (Wesentlichkeitstheorie), and thereby does not assert that the Federal Government violated or threatened to violate rights of the Bundestag within the meaning of § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act.
97
dd) The inadmissibility of these challenges (see bb) above) is not affected by the applicant’s submission that the Federal Government’s consent is not in breach of inviolable substantive constitutional principles, but that it is presently precluded by constitutional provisions which would have had to be amended by a majority capable of amending the Constitution. The major aspect raised by the applicant in this regard is national sovereignty. However, even this argument cannot lead to the desired extension of review to the substantive provisions of the Basic Law on which these claims rest.
98
If a state measure is not precluded by Art. 79(3) of the Basic Law, but ‘merely’ by a constitutional provision that can be amended, it is indeed the Bundestag, together with the Bundesrat, that can effectively remove this obstacle by way of constitutional amendment (Art. 79(2) of the Basic Law). This applies irrespective of whether the constitutional provision ‘precluding’ the act at issue only assigns the competence for the matter in question to a state organ other than the one wishing to take action – in this case, the Bundestag instead of the Federal Government – or whether the provision poses substantive obstacles which cannot be overcome by any state organ unless the provision is rescinded or amended.
99
However, the assessment in Organstreit proceedings of ‘acts performed without constitutional amendment’ in light of the Bundestag’s legislative powers only hinges on whether the constitutional provision that was not observed and whose amendment would have been necessary was, at a minimum, also intended to guarantee legislative powers of the Bundestag. The role of Organstreit proceedings is to specify the scope of the rights and obligations in relation to a potential respondent when the applicant asserts that an act or omission on the part of the respondent violates, or directly threatens to violate, rights and obligations conferred by the Basic Law on the applicant or on the organ to which the applicant belongs (Art. 93(1) no. 1 of the Basic Law; § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act).
100
As the Federal Constitutional Court recently found in proceedings involving a parliamentary group in the Bundestag and the Federal Government, this description of the types of potential subject matters of Organstreit proceedings also has the following implication: ‘Whether the conduct of the Federal Government violated the Basic Law in other respects, without violating rights of the Bundestag, cannot be decided in these proceedings’ (BVerfGE 2, 347 <368>). The decisive factor in Organstreit proceedings with the Bundestag as applicant and the Federal Government as respondent are therefore the ‘rights and obligations of the Bundestag’ conferred by the Basic Law (cf. also BVerfGE 2, 347 <366 f.>).
101
Under the Basic Law, the Bundestag acts as a legislative organ, not as an all-powerful ‘legal oversight authority’ vis-à-vis the Federal Government; the Basic Law established the Bundestag as a political authority responsible for creation, oversight and revocation in relation to the Federal Government and, in particular, the Federal Chancellor (cf. Art. 63(1), Art. 43(1), Art. 67(1) of the Basic Law and BVerfGE 2, 347 <371 before 4.>). Therefore, there is no right of the Bundestag that can be derived from the Basic Law that would compel the Federal Government to refrain from all substantively or formally unconstitutional acts.
102
‘Rights of the Bundestag’ within the meaning of § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act only mean those rights conferred upon the Bundestag that the Bundestag can exercise itself or in the exercise of which it can participate, or rights that must be respected to ensure that the Bundestag can exercise its competences and the validity of its acts (such as the declaration of a state of defence under Art. 115a(1) of the Basic Law). The mere fact that a challenged act might violate the Basic Law is not sufficient for an applicant that has the legal ability to be a party to the proceedings to also have standing. An applicant in Organstreit proceedings cannot seek an abstract review of the constitutionality of the respondent’s conduct independent of the applicant’s own rights. Rather, an application in Organstreit proceedings can only be admissible if the provision of the Basic Law that is claimed to be violated confers a right on the applicant. Nor does such a right within the meaning of § 64 of the Federal Constitutional Court Act accrue to the Bundestag from any provision of the Basic Law in light of its Art. 79(1) and (2) solely because these provisions can only be amended or rescinded with the involvement of the Bundestag. The Bundestag only has standing to challenge a violation of a Basic Law provision in cases where the provision itself gives rise to rights or obligations within the meaning of § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act, and does not have standing simply because such provisions can only be amended with the involvement of the Bundestag. The applicant’s assertions to that effect are not capable of conferring standing on it in this regard. A violation of rights of the Bundestag under Art. 79 of the Basic Law, or a threat thereof, is not at issue here.
103
There is no need to decide in the present proceedings whether the Federal Government’s consent to the deployment of Pershing-2 missiles with nuclear warheads and cruise missiles on German territory is compatible with the Basic Law in all respects; rather, the decision only concerns the question of whether the consent violated or threatened to violate rights of the Bundestag within the meaning of § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act.
104
4. […]
105-113
5. […]
114
The applicant has the necessary recognised legal interest in bringing proceedings.
115-119
[…]
C.
120
The application is unfounded.
121
With the challenged declaration of consent, the Federal Government neither violated nor threatened to violate rights of the Bundestag following from Art. 59(2) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 20(3) of the Basic Law or from Art. 79(1) first sentence in conjunction with Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law.
I.
122
It is not disputed that the Federal Government has given its consent to the deployment of the weapon systems in question on the territory of the Federal Republic of Germany, and that no specific law that would have provided express authorisation to give such consent was enacted.
123
The challenged consent was given in the framework of the NATO defence system. Its legal basis consists of the North Atlantic Treaty of 4 April 1949 (as amended on 17 October 1951 – Federal Law Gazette, Bundesgesetzblatt – BGBl. 1955 II p. 289), the Treaty of Brussels of 17 March 1948 on economic, social and cultural collaboration and collective self-defence (Treaty on the Western European Union [WEU] as amended on 23 October 1954 – BGBl. 1955 II p. 283) and the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces in the Federal Republic of Germany (BGBl. 1955 II p. 253). […] These treaties created the legal framework for the ‘German Defence Contribution’ to ensure the ‘defence of the free world’ referred to in Art. 4(1) of the Convention on Relations between the Three Powers and the Federal Republic of Germany (Deutschlandvertrag) and in the preamble to the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces. They are understood as a treaty system for collective self-defence within the meaning of Art. 51 of the Charter of the United Nations (cf. preamble and Arts. 3 and 7 NATO Treaty; preamble and Arts. V and VI Western European Union Treaty). Pursuant to Art. IV of the Treaty on the Western European Union, the parties ‘and any organs established by them under the Treaty shall work in close co-operation with the North Atlantic Treaty Organization. Recognising the undesirability of duplicating the Military Staffs of NATO, the Council and its agency will rely on the appropriate Military Authorities of NATO for information and advice on military matters.’
II.
124
The challenged declaration of consent is an act of defence policy within the framework of this treaty-based security alliance and its implementation; it does not possess the legal nature of an independent declaration to conclude a treaty. Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law does not apply – either directly or mutatis mutandis.
125
1. The consent in question is a declaration of legal significance given in the framework of an international treaty system; it is not a mere political declaration of intent that would not fall under the scope of application of Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law because it has no legal effect. It is irrelevant in this respect whether the Brussels Double-Track Decision was an act of the NATO Council or a special act of NATO members; the NATO members considered the decision […] to be binding.
126
The declaration of consent by the Federal Government is of legal significance because when the Federal Republic of Germany granted its final consent to the implementation of the Double-Track Decision on 16 November 1983, it gave the United States of America, in its capacity as a NATO ally, permission under international law to deploy the weapon systems in question in the specified scale on German territory. […]
127
2. The challenged declaration of consent was not part of the conclusion of an international treaty. It is true that it cannot be ruled out that acts by organs or collective acts of international treaty organisations can also constitute treaties of the member states with the same contents as the acts in question if they are undertaken with this intention. For example, the Member States of the European Communities occasionally use this form, particularly to overcome potential competence deficits of the Communities or put them beyond dispute. However, there must be specific indications that such a dual function exists.
128
In the present case, no indications or circumstances are ascertainable that would suggest that the Federal Government’s declaration of consent could have been directed at concluding a bi- or multilateral treaty regarding the deployment of the weapon systems in question. Such indications also cannot be derived from either the statement of 12 December 1979 regarding the ‘Double-Track Decision’ or the conduct of the United States as the potential other party to the treaty.
129
3. There are no ascertainable grounds for the assumption that the Federal Government’s declaration was invalid under international law and therefore could not be binding on the Federal Republic of Germany. The Ministers of Foreign Affairs and Defence representing Germany were authorised to make this declaration under German constitutional law, by virtue of a mandate implicitly granted by the Federal President to represent him in his capacity as the organ responsible for making such a declaration under Art. 59(1) first sentence of the Basic Law ([…]). Moreover, under general international law, the Minister of Foreign Affairs of a state is authorised to make binding declarations – including of the type at issue here (cf., e.g., Art. 7(2)(a) Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties of 23 May 1969). It cannot be ascertained that the declaration had other deficiencies under international law.
130
In its order of 16 December 1983 (BVerfGE 66, 39 <64 f.>), the Senate found that the challenged declaration of consent does not violate ius cogens rules of international law. The applicant did not demonstrate any general practice and opinio juris in the practice of states to that effect; the Senate concurs with the assessment of the international law situation as presented by the Federal Government’s legal representative.
131
4. Declarations under international law of the present type do not require the consent or involvement of the legislative bodies in the form of a federal law pursuant to Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law.
132
a) In German state practice, unilateral declarations of intent under international law given in the framework of existing bi- or multilateral treaties have never been subject to such a consent requirement. The same applies to other unilateral declarations of intent under international law, with the exception of special cases such as declarations under international law regarding a state of defence pursuant to Art. 115a(5) of the Basic Law. For example, the Federal Republic of Germany has recognised numerous foreign states, severed diplomatic relations with foreign states, claimed the German continental shelf and fishing zones in the North Sea and the Baltic Sea and terminated international treaties without obtaining the consent of the Bundestag in the form of a federal law. This practice is in line with the views held by a majority of legal scholars ([…]).
133
b) Expanding the requirement of consent under Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law to acts other than declarations to conclude a treaty is not compatible with the wording of the provision. Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law also cannot be applied to such acts by way of analogy.
134
Consistent with Art. 45(3) of the Weimar Constitution and its application, according to which unilateral acts under international law such as the termination of international treaties were considered to not require the consent of the Reichstag ([…]), Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law […] expressly limits the requirement of legislative approval to certain types of international treaties. Thus, an agreement under international law that does not fall under the term ‘political treaty’ and does not concern matters of federal legislation is not covered by Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law, including when it has significant effects on the internal relations of the Federal Republic of Germany (cf. BVerfGE 1, 372 <382>; […]).
135
It is irrelevant here whether this finding alone would be capable of ruling out that Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law is applied mutatis mutandis to declarations of the type at issue here. In any case, such an application would raise serious concerns with regard to the position of Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law in the Basic Law’s allocation of state tasks to specific functions and the bodies performing these functions.
136
To be certain, Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law – like several other provisions of the Basic Law – grants the Bundestag certain powers of participation regarding the formation of the will for undertaking acts in foreign affairs. These matters, for which involvement of the Bundestag as well as the form of action of such involvement are guaranteed by constitutional law, are of such significance, both in political and in legal terms, that they cannot be viewed as exceptions. From a historical perspective, these rules reflect a trend towards strengthening parliamentary involvement in the formation of the will in foreign affairs. Nevertheless, Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law limits this involvement, both in subject matter, to treaties of the type defined in this provision, and in terms of substance, to mere consent in the form of a federal law. Under Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law, the Bundestag cannot prevent the Federal Government from refraining from, starting or breaking off treaty negotiations or drafting treaties with specific contents, nor can it compel the Federal Government to do these things. Likewise, the Bundestag cannot require the executive to conclude a treaty for which an act of approval within the meaning of Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law has been adopted or, after such treaty is concluded, to terminate the treaty under international law or maintain it; the special provision regarding the conclusion of peace in Art. 115l(3) of the Basic Law notwithstanding. Apart from the power to provide or not provide constitutional authorisation to the executive, in the form of a law, to conclude treaties of the aforementioned type, Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law does not grant the legislative bodies powers to initiate, shape or oversee foreign affairs. Nor does it follow that, as claimed by the applicant, each act of the Federal Government under international law that governs the political relations of the Federal Republic of Germany or concerns matters of federal legislation must be in the form of an international treaty that requires the consent of the legislator.
137
The strict limitation of the powers granted to the legislative bodies by Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law is an element of the separation of powers as shaped by the Basic Law. Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law must be interpreted in light of Art. 20(2) of the Basic Law. The principle of the organisational and functional division and separation of powers set out in that provision serves to ensure the distribution of political power and responsibility as well as oversight of persons in power; it also serves to ensure that state decisions are made as correctly as possible, i.e. by the organs that are best suited for making such decisions in terms of their organisation, composition, function and procedures. It also has an overall aim to moderate state power. The concentration of political power that would arise if the Bundestag were granted central, executive-style decision-making powers for foreign affairs which exceed those assigned to it by the Basic Law would run counter to the present division of power, responsibility and oversight provided for by the Basic Law. The fact that at the federal level it is only members of the Bundestag who are directly elected by the people does not change this. The specific allocation and balancing of state power that must be observed under the Basic Law may not be undermined by parliamentary monism in the form of an absolute reservation of parliamentary decision-making that is falsely derived from the principle of democracy (BVerfGE 49, 89 <124 ff.>). The principle that Government is accountable to Parliament also requires that the Government have a core of autonomous executive decision-making (BVerfGE 67, 100 <139>). Democracy under the Basic Law is governed by the rule of law and, for the relations between state organs this means above all a democracy involving the separation of powers.
138
In light of the exceptional significance that foreign policy currently has for the existence of the Federal Republic of Germany, an extension of the scope of Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law to acts of the Federal Government vis-à-vis other subjects of international law that do not involve international treaties, including acts governing political relations, would amount to an encroachment on central decision-making powers of the executive. Such an extension would shift a substantial amount of political power to the Bundestag at the expense of the executive and would do so in an area that, in functional terms, does not constitute legislation within the meaning of Art. 20(2) second sentence of the Basic Law. This is because the acts under international law in question here are not themselves capable of bringing about domestic legal effects. The general allocation of acts in foreign policy matters to the executive government’s sphere of competence is based on the consideration that, from an institutional perspective, it is generally only the Federal Government that permanently has the necessary personnel, resources and organisational structure to react swiftly and adequately to changing foreign policy situations and is therefore best suited to fulfil the state’s responsibility of dealing with foreign affairs. The trend towards more parliamentary involvement in foreign affairs, which is reflected in Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law, does not run counter to this allocation. Under the Basic Law, the executive organs also derive democratic legitimation for their institutions and functions from the constitutional legislator’s fundamental decision in Art. 20(2) of the Basic Law (BVerfGE 49, 89 <125>). These organs also have democratic legitimation in terms of their members, which is conveyed through a chain of individual acts of appointment and dismissal that can be traced back to active citizens, in particular under Arts. 38, 63, 64 and 67 of the Basic Law ([…]).
139
The Basic Law’s principle of democracy therefore cannot be invoked as grounds for expanding the requirement of consent under Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law to acts of the type in question here.
140
This is not altered by the fact that such acts of the executive may be binding on Germany under international law in the individual case and that these binding effects are difficult or impossible to escape, or produce other effects which are difficult or impossible to escape; whether this is the case for the consent in question therefore need not be decided here. It is true that the requirement of Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law – that treaties of the type described therein require legislative consent to be concluded – has the purpose of preventing permanent or indissoluble binding effects under international law without the consent of the Bundestag. This could be an argument in favour of expanding its application, or applying it mutatis mutandis to acts under international law of a certain scope that do not involve treaties. Nor could it be argued that such far-reaching effects under international law rarely result from acts not involving treaties; the recognition of foreign states, of territorial changes, borders and other sovereignty lines or of legal relationships under international law, for example, may well have similarly far-reaching significance and are, if made without reservation, in principle irrevocable. Declarations made in the framework of NATO’s consultation process can be equally significant, too.
141
However, as set out above, the organisation of democracy under the Basic Law does not require that all acts and decisions that are of far-reaching or existential significance in themselves or with regard to their effects must be assigned to Parliament, or that Parliament must be involved through legislation. The executive, and in particular the Government, is also a ‘political’ power; it is not limited from the outset to decisions of lesser significance. Under the Basic Law, state power in all its functions is democratically constituted and legitimated, albeit in different ways, and is organised on this basis in line with the principle of the separation of powers. It therefore does not amount to a democratic deficit that the executive has exclusive powers in foreign affairs to take far-reaching and, possibly, existential decisions. Potential political risks resulting from this division of competences must be accepted under constitutional law.
142
If the Bundestag disapproves of such decisions, it can make use of its parliamentary oversight powers – including in foreign affairs. The Bundestag can elect a new Federal Chancellor, and thus bring down the government, it can make use of its budgetary powers, but Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law does not grant the Bundestag the power to grant or deny consent to acts of the type in question here.
III.
143
The act in question does not violate Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law.
144
1. By giving its consent, the Federal Republic of Germany has permitted the United States of America, as a partner in a treaty-based defensive alliance and within the alliance’s legal framework, to deploy a specific number of Pershing-2 missiles with nuclear warheads and cruise missiles on the territory of the Federal Republic of Germany, as set forth in the Decision of the Foreign and Defence Ministers of the NATO States of 12 December 1979. In accordance with the directions agreed to by the NATO allies, the power to authorise the military use of these weapon systems lies with the President of the United States of America; in any case, he must consult the allies prior to operations of a selective nature, with particular regard to be given to the opinion of those allies from whose soil the weapons will potentially be launched or who are providing the means of delivery or the nuclear warhead. This consultation procedure may be dispensed with if required due to exigencies of time or other extreme situations, such as defence against a surprise attack. Under the current command structure of NATO, the power to use the systems in question in military operations lies with the Supreme Allied Commander Europe (SACEUR) when operational command is activated. This decision-making structure takes into account that the United States has the greatest nuclear arsenal among the NATO allies and is therefore particularly able, and has a duty, to ensure protection of the allies against attack.
145
a) The authorisation to deploy the US weapon systems in question on the territory of the Federal Republic of Germany does not in itself amount to a transfer of sovereign powers within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law; with this authorisation, Germany did not withdraw an exclusive sovereign right that had previously existed, or could legally have existed, in favour of a foreign power (cf. BVerfGE 37, 271 <280> 59, 63 <90>). The authorisation does not result in additional restrictions on Germany’s territorial sovereignty or its sovereignty vis-à-vis citizens. What is decisive, however, is that, in the Federal Government’s view ([…]), the right to decide on the use of these systems is ‘part of the deployment’ and inextricably linked to it.
146
This legal effect is tantamount to a transfer of sovereign powers within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law. For the period of validity of the challenged declaration of consent, the authorisation to deploy these weapons and use them in military operations from German territory cannot be determined by the Federal Republic of Germany alone; in this respect, Germany has set aside its previous exclusive authority in favour of non-German public power, especially in view of the integrated command structure of NATO. This is not altered by the fact that the Federal Republic of Germany had previously undertaken, under Art. 2 of the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons of 1 July 1968 (BGBl. 1974 II p. 786), to not receive control over nuclear weapons or nuclear explosive devices directly or indirectly and to not manufacture or otherwise acquire nuclear weapons or other nuclear explosive devices. In comparison to this obligation, which must be interpreted in light of Art. 51 of the UN Charter, the consent in question here constitutes an independent legal basis in the framework of the alliance system; it would be unaffected by a termination of the Non-Proliferation Treaty.
147
b) These sovereign powers were not per se transferred to the United States of America. If this were the case, Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law would not apply, at least not directly, given that it concerns the transfer of sovereign powers to an ‘international organisation’.
148
The challenged declaration of consent grants the United States of America the decision on authorising the use of the weapon systems in question only in its capacity as an ally under the NATO Treaties and, in particular, subject to the consultations agreed for such authorisations and the joint doctrines for operations and planning. The consent only covers the weapon systems in question as weapons of NATO, with the resulting restrictions of their use for the tasks and purposes of NATO.
149
At least from the constitutional perspective of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law, this situation arising from the Treaties must be interpreted to the effect that the President of the United States of America is entrusted with a special NATO function; insofar as the President takes a decision on authorisation that is within the framework of the declaration of consent by the Federal Government that is challenged here, the President can be considered to act as a special organ of NATO. Moreover, significant international law aspects also indicate that such action by the President of the United States of America would be attributable to NATO as a whole.
150
This constitutional outcome is also supported by the fact that the Brussels Decision of the Foreign and Defence Ministers of the NATO States of 12 December 1979, under no. 7, addresses the LRTNF (long range theatre nuclear forces) potential of NATO. Furthermore, delivery systems such as the warheads whose deployment was consented to by the Federal Government are managed by units of the United States Armed Forces in the Federal Republic of Germany; they are included in the operational planning of the integrated NATO command staffs and, under the current command structure, are under the control of the Supreme Allied Commander Europe (SACEUR) when operational command is activated.
151
c) Insofar as it results in legal effects for authorisation and decision-making with regard to deployment in military operations, the challenged declaration of consent amounts to a transfer of sovereign powers, within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law, to NATO. This is not altered by the fact that NATO’s Supreme Allied Commander Europe, based on previous practice, is also a US military officer and therefore subject to the command of the United States of America. As set out above, the challenged consent of the Federal Government only concerns the stationing and use of the weapon systems in question in the framework of the NATO system.
152
aa) NATO is an international organisation within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law. This is largely undisputed in legal scholarship. The assumption that the challenged declaration of consent transferred sovereign powers to NATO within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law is not rebutted by the fact that the NATO Treaty leaves it to each contracting party to assess whether a situation is a case of mutual defence within the meaning of Art. 5(1) and, if so, in what way the party satisfies its mutual defence obligation, or by the fact that NATO command staffs are not in command of the forces assigned to them by the member states for operational planning in the framework of the relevant decisions of the North Atlantic Council unless operational command is activated; it is also not rebutted by the fact that the decisions of the North Atlantic Council in principle only amount to recommendations, the assignment of armed forces for operational planning may be revoked by individual member states, or that the Treaty, according to its Art. 11 first sentence, is carried out by the parties ‘in accordance with their respective constitutional processes’. Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law does not mandate that the relinquishment of German sovereign power to an international organisation be irrevocable. Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law also does not require that the current exercise of transferred sovereign powers may not be subject to specific assessments of international situations made independently by the member states of the international organisation.
153
Rather, what is decisive is that the German act of transfer constitutes an essential legal basis in the event that these sovereign powers are actually exercised. This is the case here. The challenged declaration of consent is a legally essential prerequisite, in the framework of the alliance system, for granting the United States, in its capacity as a NATO ally and subject to the legal obligations of the alliance system, permission to decide on the authorisation of use, and for granting the competent integrated military commands of the alliance permission to decide on the military operations of the weapon systems stationed on German territory. This is not altered by the fact that this decision-making power may only become relevant in the future and, in the framework of the alliance system, depends on other factual and procedural conditions being fulfilled before it may be used. The Federal Government’s declaration of consent legally permits the use of this authorisation under the Treaty; this by itself amounts to a transfer of sovereign powers within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law.
154
It cannot be derived from Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law that a transfer of sovereign powers would require that integrated NATO command posts have direct command over German armed forces or inhabitants even before operational command was activated. Nor can it be inferred from the provision that a transfer of sovereign powers must only be assumed to have taken place when the international organisation in question has been granted powers with direct legal consequences vis-à-vis individuals. It therefore need not be decided here whether, in view of the current assignment of Bundeswehr units to NATO, direct command also extends to decisions regarding the use of the weapon systems in question once operational command has been activated.
155
The applicability of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law is also not precluded by the fact that the Federal Republic of Germany’s involvement in the decision to authorise the use of the weapon systems in question is formally limited to the consultation process, and that Germany does not have co-decision rights – not even in the form of veto rights. As set out above, this decision-making structure reflects the special role of the United States of America as the alliance’s nuclear superpower and the policy of non-proliferation that the Federal Republic of Germany has committed to in treaties. At least for this very politically sensitive area, it cannot be inferred from Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law that formal co-decision rights for the Federal Republic of Germany are required for the transfer of sovereign powers. It is irrelevant here whether a transfer would be permissible if any German influence on decisions of the international organisations were ruled out, or if the Federal Republic of Germany were discriminated against compared to other, similar states. Neither is the case here.
156
bb) The Federal Government itself does not consider the consent given to be a transfer of sovereign powers within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law; this, however, does not preclude a different constitutional assessment by the Federal Constitutional Court. The Federal Constitutional Court does not assign a different meaning under international law to the challenged declaration of consent than that ascribed to it by the Federal Government. There is no need to decide here whether, as the respondent asserts, the alliance system at issue is a system of mutual collective security within the meaning of Art. 24(2) of the Basic Law, and the Federal Republic of Germany has, through its declaration of consent, agreed to restrictions of its sovereign powers within the framework of this system.
157
2. The transfer of sovereign powers at issue here is also compatible with Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law in substantive terms; it did not require a prior change in the wording of the Basic Law, nor does it breach the limits of Art. 79(3) of the Basic Law.
158
a) Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law does allow the Federal Republic of Germany to provide territory in the context of a defensive alliance for the stationing of allied armed forces and to permit command structures for a deployment of these armed forces that serves the defence purpose of the alliance.
159
In the past, part of the nature of traditional military alliances was that armed forces of other allies had rights of passage, residence and deployment on the territory of an ally without being subject to the sovereign authority of that ally or integrated into its armed forces. This may have led to temporary restrictions of the sovereignty of the ally concerned, but such restrictions were an essential prerequisite for the protection said ally sought from the alliance – for example, because it lacked sufficient military power of its own.
160
Today, too, the stationing of foreign armed forces and the transfer of sovereign powers this entails serve to ensure the Federal Republic of Germany’s protection against attacks and thus serve to uphold the integrity of its constitutional order and its sovereignty. This was evidently assumed both by the legislator, when it gave its consent to the alliance system, and by the Federal Government, when it made its declaration of consent challenged here. At the oral hearing, the Federal Government, represented by the Federal Minister of Defence, set out its view that the Soviet side was engaged in an arms race which had neither been provoked by Western defence measures nor justified by Soviet security interests, and which, in particular, called into question the strategic unity of the alliance in Europe; in view of the Soviet position on the question of establishing an approximate balance in medium-range weapons, the alliance had had no choice but to begin now with the deployment of the weapon systems in question, which had been agreed to in 1979.
161
It is for the Federal Government to make assessments and evaluations of this kind. The only limit set on this power by the Basic Law is in the case of manifest arbitrariness. If this absolute limit is not crossed, the Federal Constitutional Court does not conduct a review of whether assessments or evaluations of this kind are correct, given that no legal standards exist in this respect; rather, the Federal Government must assume political responsibility for these assessments and evaluations.
162
In the present case, it cannot be found that constitutional limits have been breached.
163
b) Under Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law, a decision of whether and to what extent sovereign powers are to be transferred to an international organisation may only be taken by the legislator. The transfer is carried out through acts of international law; the authorisation to do so must be given ‘by a law’. This constitutional requirement has been satisfied in the present case by the Act on the Accession of the Federal Republic of Germany to the Brussels Treaty and the North Atlantic Treaty of 24 March 1955 (BGBl. II p. 256) and by the Act concerning the Convention of 23 October 1954 on the Presence of Foreign Forces in the Federal Republic of Germany of 24 March 1955 (BGBl. II p. 253); both Acts must be seen in the context of the alliance system, of which the underlying treaties form part.
164
The Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces in the Federal Republic of Germany is a legal basis for the stationing of allied armed forces on German territory ([…]). The authorisation to station armed forces on German territory was granted to the parties of this Convention in view of their role as members of NATO and the obligations entailed by it. This follows from the historical context of the conclusion of both treaties with the Federal Republic of Germany; the wording of the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces, too, in particular its Art. 1(4) and the explanatory memorandum to the Government’s draft of the act of approval (loc. cit., in particular the preamble) also indicate that this was intended by the parties.
165
The challenged declaration of consent is covered by statutory authorisation:
166
aa) (1) The North Atlantic Treaty does not contain any provisions that expressly grant the powers set forth in the declaration of consent to NATO. However, it does not follow that the requirements of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law have not been satisfied in the present case. As the Senate held in its order of 23 June 1981 (BVerfGE 58, 1 <36 f.>), the substantive scope of the requirement of a statutory provision (Gesetzesvorbehalt) in Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law must also be determined in view of the manner in which organisations at international level within the meaning of this provision are established and work. This typically occurs in the framework of an integration process. Over the course of this process, several individual acts of implementation are necessary to bring about the situation sought in the founding treaty. These may take diverse legal forms. Even where the founding treaty itself did not determine the contents, form and timing of the integration process, no specific law within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law is required for each individual step of implementation from the outset. Such laws can be dispensed with where the founding treaty, endorsed by an act of approval, set out the future process of implementation in a sufficiently specific manner. That said, fundamental changes to the integration agenda and its implementation are not covered by the original act of approval under Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law. The standards regarding such sufficient specificity must be derived from the particular nature of the matters set out in the founding treaty in light of the legal interests protected by Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law and of the latitude granted by the provision and its practicability at international level.
167
(2) Measured against these standards, the transfer of powers for the use of the weapon systems stationed in the Federal Republic of Germany by means of the challenged declaration of consent given by the Federal Government did not require a separate law under Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law.
168
In the preamble to the North Atlantic Treaty, the parties resolved to unite their efforts for collective defence and the preservation of peace and security. In order more effectively to achieve the objectives of the Treaty, they agreed in Art. 3 that they separately and jointly, by means of continuous and effective self-help and mutual aid, will maintain and develop their individual and collective capacity to resist armed attack. Art. 9 provides that the NATO Council shall establish immediately a defence committee which shall recommend measures for the implementation of Art. 3 and Art. 5, with the latter including a mutual defence clause in case of armed attack. The aforementioned preamble and provisions show that one of the fundamental premises of the North Atlantic Treaty is the possibility of a progressive organisation and integration of defence efforts and defence forces for the protected territory. That this agenda set out in the Treaty is not described in greater detail and the political and legal process in which it can be realised is not more precisely defined is due to the particular nature of the subject matter covered by the Treaty. The proper organisation of joint defence and the measures necessary to this end cannot be conclusively determined in advance given the ongoing changes in the political and strategic environment the allies face individually and together, such as changes in the political and strategic forces, or the notion of what constitutes a possible aggressor, and in view of the constant change in other circumstances of significance for security policy, such as the advancement in weapons technology and weaponry from whatever side. Detailed Treaty provisions on strategic concepts and plans, or the organisation, type, scale and stationing of armed forces and their weapons as well as command structures could very quickly become obsolete under the current circumstances in view of the Treaty’s objective of guaranteeing security and peace for the parties. The subject matter of the alliance treaties is characterised by such dynamic developments. If the purpose of the alliance is to be achieved, it must be possible to take rapid and adaptable measures for which the content and legal forms cannot be fully determined in advance. Only relatively open provisions, such as the ones contained in the North Atlantic Treaty, are suitable for achieving this aim. In light of the foregoing, the North Atlantic Pact is a body of treaties that delineates the possible integration agenda within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law in a sufficiently specific manner. Measures taken within this alliance framework do not require separate consent in the form of a law pursuant to Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law, they also do not require an ‘amendment’ of the statutory authorisation. So is the case here.
169
The agenda of military integration was sufficiently clear to the legislator when it adopted the Act on the Accession of the Federal Republic of Germany to the Brussels Treaty and the North Atlantic Treaty. At the Conference of the Nine Powers held in London from 28 September to 3 October 1954, the powers present at the conference, all members of NATO, agreed under Section IV of the Final Act to recommend that NATO strengthen its organisation by providing that all forces of NATO countries stationed in Europe in principle ‘shall be placed under the authority’ of SACEUR. When the Bundestag adopted its decision, it was aware of the wording of this agreement (cf. Bundestag document, Bundestagsdrucksache – BTDrucks. II/ 1000, p. 50), and of the resolution of the North Atlantic Council to implement this section of the Final Act of the London Conference (cf. BTDrucks. II/1061, p. 61 ff.). The Federal Government’s explanatory memorandum to the Draft Act on the Accession of the Federal Republic of Germany to the Brussels Treaty and the North Atlantic Treaty makes reference to ‘integrated forces’ (BTDrucks. II/1061, p. 47), and the Special Report of the Committee on European Security Matters mentions a ‘uniform organisation’ through integration and joint command posts (BTDrucks. II/1200, p. 50; […]).
170
Nor did the Bundestag, in adopting this Act, express explicit or implicit reservations as to the type and scale of the weaponry to be provided to forces or as to the potential powers of NATO regarding the use of certain types of weapons, in particular nuclear weapons, from German territory. In particular, when adopting this Act, the legislator was aware of the storage of nuclear weapons on German territory ([…]). There are no indications in the act of approval that the Bundestag meant to rule out powers of NATO organs to use nuclear weapons stationed on German territory, or to make such use subject to a separate law.
171
(3) Even if it were presumed that the applicant’s submissions were correct, in that there was a new strategic dimension to the weapon systems in question and their deployment on German territory, this would not amount to a fundamental change of the NATO agenda to which the legislator consented when the Federal Republic of Germany joined NATO. The basic objective of NATO as a defensive alliance, as laid down in the aforementioned treaties, remains unaffected. The legislator did not fail to see that over the course of such a long-term defensive alliance (cf. Art. 13 NATO Treaty, Art. XII(3) Western European Union Treaty) risks and strategic situations can change – sometimes quite rapidly – given the aforementioned dynamic political situations and technological developments and that doctrines and strategies regarding defence policy and the military must remain adaptable if the purpose of the alliance is to be achieved. It cannot be inferred from the Basic Law or the acts of approval of the aforementioned treaties that acts of the Federal Government in the framework of the alliance system, such as those challenged by the applicant, therefore require specific statutory authorisation. The applicant has not asserted that the Federal Government’s declaration of consent reflects its intent to launch an attack and that therefore this declaration both violated Art. 26(1) first sentence of the Basic Law and exceeded the authorisation framework of the aforementioned acts of approval; nor are there any indications to this effect. Beyond these legal limits, however, it is for the executive, which has the power to make assessments and act in foreign and defence policy matters, to assess such situations, developments and risks and to make decisions. It is irrelevant in this respect whether and to what extent the legislator could impose particular statutory requirements on the executive for such assessments and decisions in light of Art. 20(2) of the Basic Law – it did not do so here.
172
In particular, the fact that the Federal Government does not share the applicant’s view that the purported new strategic dimension of the weapon systems in question and the computer-controlled and thus error-prone warning systems that are allegedly necessary considerably increase the risk of a pre-emptive nuclear attack by the Soviet Union or the risk of accidentally causing nuclear war does not exceed the constitutional limits of the executive powers of assessment.
173
In the Federal Government’s view, if the Soviet Union intended to launch a pre-emptive nuclear attack, it would have to expect a counterattack by NATO; the Soviet Union’s precautions against such a counterattack would have to be so extensive that they could not remain hidden from Western reconnaissance. According to the Federal Government, there was therefore no increased risk of a pre-emptive attack by the Soviet Union on the weapon systems stationed in the Federal Republic of Germany, especially since the mobility of these systems also ruled out the possibility that they could all be disabled by a surprise attack. No constitutional deficiencies of this assessment are ascertainable; nor does it violate the legal obligations arising from the NATO treaties.
174
The same applies to the Federal Government’s view that the technical features of the weapon systems in question increased their deterrent effect and, precisely for this reason, did not lower the threshold for nuclear war, and its view regarding the question of whether the weapon systems’ stationing would make NATO capable of launching a decapitating or paralysing strike against the Soviet Union. At the oral hearing, the Federal Minister of Defence stated that NATO was not interested in dealing with conflicts through fighting, but intended to settle conflicts by political means as quickly as possible, and was therefore committed to keeping open communication channels with leadership of unfriendly states; this statement rules out the finding that this assessment is erroneous under constitutional law.
175
This also applies to the Federal Government’s view that error-prone technical systems would not result in ‘accidental war’. In the past, errors in technical systems have not led to critical situations, let alone serious preparations for the use of nuclear weapons. According to the Federal Government, there were no indications whatsoever that plans were underway, whether in NATO states or in the Soviet Union, to leave the final decision on the use of nuclear weapons to a computer-controlled automatic mechanism. Agreements between the Soviet Union and the United States of America have served to prevent accidental outbreaks of war. No constitutional errors are evident with regard to this assessment; it is not for the Federal Constitutional Court to decide whether it is correct in other respects or whether other assessments are possible.
176
Nor does a fundamental change of the NATO agenda that the legislator consented when it decided to join the alliance system result from the applicant’s view that the Federal Government, in giving its consent, brought about a situation in which the President of the United States could make German territory the basis for military reprisals against the Soviet Union if a Soviet attack on the United States of America were launched on the territory specified in Art. 6 of the North Atlantic Treaty. According to the applicant, this would take competences away from the Federal Government, the Bundestag and the Bundesrat and hand them over to the organ of a foreign state, which could then bring about the prerequisites for the declaration of a state of defence within the meaning of Art. 115a of the Basic Law and thereby force upon the Federal Republic of Germany the decision to assist its partners by military means within the scope of the mutual defence clause.
177
The legislator that gave its consent to Germany’s accession to NATO was aware of the possibility of such a situation, in view of the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces and the presence of US forces on German territory based thereon (see bb) below), just as the Constitution-amending legislator of 1968, which inserted Art. 115a into the Basic Law, was aware of it (BGBl. I p. 709). It is a central plank of the North Atlantic Treaty (Art. 5(1)) and of the Treaty on the Western European Union (Art. V) that an armed attack against one of the parties is to be considered an attack against them all and triggers the mutual defence obligation. This notwithstanding, there is no reason to doubt that the parties to such a conflict will do everything possible to limit it, including and especially with regard to nuclear weapons; this is in keeping with the spirit of the alliance. The Federal Government’s consent to the stationing of new weapons on German territory did not change this. The legal possibility for the Federal Republic of Germany to assess whether something constitutes an attack and which measures it considers to be ‘necessary’ in such a case to restore and maintain the security of the North Atlantic territory is not curtailed; likewise, the competences granted to the Bundestag by Art. 115a of the Basic Law are not diminished. The actual alternatives available to the Federal Republic of Germany may be very limited in such a scenario; however, this is not because its legal possibilities have been curtailed, but because of the factual situation and the circumstance that, as can be inferred from the spirit of the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces, military defence measures of an attacked party may also be authorised from German territory. It cannot be ascertained that the challenged declaration of consent brought about a fundamental change to NATO’s agenda in this respect.
178
This outcome could also not be changed by the view that the challenged declaration of consent de facto enabled the United States to use the weapon systems in question from German territory in a manner contrary to international law and the principles of the alliance by, for example, using them against attacks not covered by the territorial scope of NATO. Notwithstanding the question of how such an assumption could be refuted by a law authorising the approval as called for by the applicant, it was for the Federal Government to assess whether a NATO partner would comply with international law and the legal limits of the alliance and the consent given within its framework. By consenting to the deployment of the weapon systems, the Federal Government clearly considered that this would be the case. The Bundestag did the same when it consented to the treaties in 1955 with the knowledge that tactical nuclear weapons were stored on German territory. The applicant did not state any facts that would suggest that this assessment is erroneous under constitutional law; nor can such facts be otherwise ascertained. The Federal Government could base its assessment on the long-standing conduct of the alliance and its parties, which does not urgently and obviously suggest another conclusion. In Europe, no armed interventions against any state have been made by the alliance and its parties, whether with conventional or with nuclear weapons. The mere possibility that parties to international treaties can act in breach of these treaties cannot be ruled out. If the Basic Law precluded such situations in order to prevent potential breaches of international law, then the Federal Republic of Germany would be largely unable to act with regard to international treaties.
179
bb) The consent regarding the stationing of new weapon systems on German territory given in the framework of the alliance system is also within the limits of the authorisation provided by the act of approval of the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces, which must be considered in the context of the alliance system.
180
These weapons are handled by US forces assigned to NATO in the Federal Republic of Germany; the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces is a legal basis for their presence in Germany. Whether these weapons increase the effective strength of these forces within the meaning of Art. 1(2) of the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces need not be decided here. This is because the Federal Government in any case gave its consent, which is required pursuant to the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces.
181
This consent is within the limits of the authorisation given by the act of approval of the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces. This follows from the same considerations as those set out for the act of approval of the North Atlantic Treaty. The stationing of allied troops and their weapons on German territory is the essential purpose of the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces.
182
cc) In addition, it must be noted that the Constitution-amending legislator, knowing about Germany’s membership of NATO, did not see any reason, particularly when including an express requirement of a statutory provision by inserting Art. 80a(3) into the Basic Law by the Act of 24 June 1968 (BGBl. I p. 709) and also when inserting Art. 45a (old version) and Art. 87a (old version) by the Act of 19 March 1956 (BGBl. I p. 111), to include a special requirement of a statutory provision in the Basic Law to which declarations of consent of the type challenged here would be subject. The legislator at the time was clearly aware of the stationing of US forces with nuclear weapons in Germany, in the framework of NATO, and of the fundamental way decision-making structures and lines of command are designed within NATO. Due to the need for the most effective defence possible, the details of such structures and lines of command are classified and subject to ongoing development; insofar as these details were explained to the Federal Constitutional Court by the respondent in the oral hearing, it cannot be ascertained that they amount to fundamental changes to the integration agenda consented to by the legislator upon Germany’s accession to NATO.
IV.
183
The declaration of consent regarding the deployment of medium-range nuclear missiles on German territory also does not violate rights of the Bundestag on the grounds that this declaration amounts to a decision of significance for the state as a whole in the sense of a key political decision. The fact that this consent is an act that is significant for the Federal Republic of Germany as a whole does not give rise to a special legislative power of the Bundestag in light of the express provisions on the competences for foreign affairs. Nor does such a power, which would override the provisions on competences, arise from the Basic Law’s principle of democracy. Under the democratic, parliamentary order laid down by the Basic Law, the government has democratic legitimation, in both institutional and functional terms (BVerfGE 49, 89 <124 ff.>). Moreover, it has democratic legitimation in terms of its members, and is subject to democratic, parliamentary oversight.
184
The Basic Law does not provide for an all-encompassing requirement of a statutory provision, nor does it contain a rule on competences stipulating that all ‘objectively essential’ decisions must be taken by the legislator. Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law and Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law are exhaustive with regard to the matters covered; the requirement of a law therefore cannot arise independently from the aspect of a decision being essential, for example in the sense of a decision of considerable political scope. The concept of a ‘guarantee of correctness’ provided by the parliamentary process due to the comparably transparent decision-making processes involved also cannot give rise to a change in the division of competences expressly provided for in the Basic Law in favour of Parliament.
185
Therefore, the consent regarding the deployment of US medium-range weapons in the Federal Republic of Germany did not require prior authorisation by the Bundestag in the form of a law from the perspective of either the principle of democracy or the significance of this act for the state as a whole.
186
This does not mean, however, that ‘objectively essential’ decisions can be taken without any involvement of the Bundestag. The Bundestag can make use of its right to ask questions, to debate and to adopt decisions, exercise its powers of scrutiny and its budgetary powers and thereby influence the Government’s decision-making, or bring down the Government by electing a new Chancellor (Art. 67(1) first sentence of the Basic Law). Moreover, in the present case, the Bundestag dealt with the question of further armament, including the consent to the deployment of the weapon systems in question, on several occasions, most recently on 22 November 1983, and expressly approved both the intended and the actual declaration of consent by the Federal Government.
V.
187
The parties to the proceedings did not submit for review the question of whether the weapon systems at issue could also be deployed on German territory by the United States without Germany’s consent, making the Federal Government’s consent irrelevant under constitutional law and raising doubts as to whether consent given nonetheless could even violate or threaten to violate rights of the Bundestag under § 64(1) of the Federal Constitutional Court Act. There is therefore no need to review whether Art. 4(2) first sentence of the Convention on Relations between the Three Powers and the Federal Republic of Germany would provide a legal basis for such action. Neither the plans to deploy the weapon systems in question nor the Brussels Decision of the Foreign and Defence Ministers of the NATO States of 12 December 1979 and its implementation in the Federal Republic of Germany were adopted in the exercise of the ‘rights heretofore exercised or held by [the Three Powers] relating to the stationing of armed forces in Germany’ so as to be able to exercise the ‘rights and responsibilities relating to Berlin and to Germany as a whole, including the reunification of Germany and a peace settlement’ reserved in Art. 2 first sentence of the Convention on Relations between the Three Powers and the Federal Republic of Germany. It clearly follows from the statement regarding the meeting of the Foreign and Defence Ministers of the NATO States of 12 December 1979 that at least the stationing of the weapon system discussed in the meeting in the Federal Republic of Germany is not based on rights reserved by the three powers.
VI.
188
The applicant’s request for taking evidence was not granted. The assertions made in nos. 1-5 of this request are, to the extent they are disputed, not relevant for the decision even assuming that they are correct. The assertions made in nos. 6 and 7 constitute political value judgments whose correctness cannot be established by taking the evidence at issue. Matters falling within the powers of assessment of the Government may not be transferred to the sphere of the judiciary by way of a taking of evidence contrary to the principle of the separation of powers.
VII.
189
The decision was taken with 7:1 votes.
- Zeidler
- Rinck
- Niebler
- Steinberger
- Träger
- Mahrenholz
- Böckenförde
- Klein
-
Dissenting opinion of Justice Mahrenholz to the Judgment of 18 December 1984- 2 BvE 13/83 -
190
In my view, the Federal Government’s consent regarding the stationing of the Pershing missiles and cruise missiles would have required a law, under both Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law and Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law.
I.
191
Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law requires a law for any transfer of sovereign powers. According to the established case-law of the Senate, a treaty transferring sovereign powers to an international organisation could give rise to a subsequent transfer of sovereign powers that are not set out in the treaty or in the act of approval without requiring new statutory authorisation only subject to strict conditions (cf. BVerfGE 58, 1). In its present decision, the Senate majority sets aside these standards in a manner that is incompatible with Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law (see II. below). Insofar as the Senate, in assessing the question of whether consent pursuant to Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law requires a law, finds that, in light of the principle of the separation of powers, Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law is only applicable to international treaties, but not to unilateral acts under international law, it would have been necessary to further assess whether the declaration of consent would have had to be part of a treaty within the meaning of Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law. The principle of the separation of powers enshrined in Art. 20(2) of the Basic Law cannot become the standard for interpreting Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law, as this provision itself is part of the framework setting out the separation of powers in the Basic Law. Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law is a specific manifestation of the general requirement of a law, according to which the legislator ‘must take all essential decisions itself’ (cf. BVerfGE 49, 89 <126 f.>). This significance of Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law would have had to be observed in the present case, too (see III. below).
II.
192
If it is assumed, as the judgment does, that NATO is an international organisation ([…]), which is not undisputed, and if it is further assumed, as the Senate does, that the President of the United States, insofar as he makes a decision on authorising the use of missiles in the framework of NATO, can be considered a special organ of the alliance ([…]), the act of approval of the underlying treaties still did not authorise the Federal Government to consent to the stationing of new US medium-range missiles.
193
The Senate’s construction amounts to saying that the legislator of the 1955 acts of approval of the North Atlantic Treaty and the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces authorised the Federal Government, for an indefinite time period, to confer upon the United States the right to station and use weapons on a scale to be determined by the United States. According to the interpretation adopted by the Senate, this authorisation applies to all conceivable political situations, even though their complexity and the dangers they pose to the existence of the German people cannot be assessed. Furthermore, this concerns all types of weapons, including weapons of a quality that was not even imaginable at the time […]. The authorisation also implies acceptance of a potentially increased risk of nuclear war that may arise from the use of this authorisation. Such an authorisation was not given through the act of approval, nor would an act of approval containing such an authorisation be compatible with Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law.
194
1. Art. 24 of the Basic Law requires rigorous adherence to form and strict application. Disagreements caused by vague legal authorisations based on Art. 80(1) of the Basic Law [for domestic authorisations] can be corrected; in international law, however, they are a strain on the relations between the Federal Republic of Germany and its partners; corrections or even the desire for them would disrupt the framework of these relations ([…]).
195
According to the Court’s view as set out in the first Eurocontrol decision, the transfer of sovereign powers constitutes an encroachment on competences determined by constitutional law, and thus a substantive constitutional amendment. Sovereign powers are transferred to organisations whose legal systems, opinion-forming processes and forms of action are not directly subject to the Basic Law and the control of the German legislator, but which, depending on their competences, can influence the German legal order with sovereign authority and with direct consequences for those subject to the law in Germany. The significance of these aspects mandates that the requirement of a law in Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law be interpreted strictly (cf. BVerfGE 58, 1 <35 f.>). In its Eurocontrol decision, the Court also took into account that the establishment of international organisations can involve an integration agenda, over the course of which many individual acts of implementation may become necessary in order to bring about the result sought by the founding treaty. Specific laws for such implementing steps can only be dispensed with where the founding treaty, endorsed by an act of approval, sets out the future process of implementation in a sufficiently specific manner (cf. loc. cit., p. 37).
196
The Senate now adopts the view that the interpretation of Art. 24 of the Basic Law also depends on the particular nature of the subject matter of the founding treaty and on the practicability of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law at international level ([…]); this view does not do justice to the purpose of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law. Formal requirements serve to provide protection and therefore cannot be interpreted in light of their practicability at international level. All the more so for formal provisions protecting the legislator’s powers particularly where sovereignty is relinquished and a de facto substantive constitutional amendment results.
197
2. The Court concedes that the North Atlantic Treaty does not contain provisions that expressly assign NATO the powers at issue. However, the Treaty also lacks an integration agenda, deemed essential by the Senate, that could set in motion a process of integration – other treaties, such as the Eurocontrol Convention and the Treaty establishing the EEC, do have such an agenda. Strictly speaking, the texts of the North Atlantic Treaty ([…]) referred to by the present judgment only serve to give the greatest possible effect to the collective character of the defensive alliance, but do not have any purpose beyond this. An integration agenda cannot be derived from them.
198
In particular, the mutual defence clause in Art. 5 cannot be considered to constitute an integration agenda or a part of such agenda because this provision, unlike Art. V of the Western European Union Treaty, does not require the parties to provide military assistance, but instead, according to the US view, which is the relevant view in this respect, allows a party to assess the mutual defence obligation in light of its own security situation ([…]): According to the United States Senate Committee on Foreign Relations, measures under Art. 5 ‘could involve anything from a diplomatic protest to the most severe forms of pressure’ ([…]). Thus, decisions regarding the way in which the mutual defence obligation is fulfilled are governed by national sovereignty.
199
The Treaty does not even contain an express statement of an intent to achieve further integration, which Art. VIII(1) of the Western European Union Treaty does contain. The difference between the North Atlantic Treaty and a military alliance seeking integration becomes even starker when compared to the Treaty establishing the European Defence Community (EDC) (BGBl. 1954, II, p. 342). The preamble of the EDC Treaty states that the most appropriate means for the maintenance of peace is:
200
as complete an integration as possible, compatible with military requirements, of the human and material elements gathered in their Defence Forces within a supranational European organisation.
201
The EDC Treaty also sought to implement this agenda: Art. 9 provides that the armed forces are those of the Community, not of the individual states; subsequent provisions only allow narrowly defined exceptions. The Treaty further provides for powers of Community organs in the sovereign sphere of the member states.
202
By contrast, under Art. 9 of the North Atlantic Treaty, the Council and the defence committee mentioned therein are limited to issuing recommendations and considering matters concerning the implementation of the Treaty. These are coordination bodies, even where their recommendations are directed at the realisation of integration structures of the military alliance ([…]).
203
The so-called protective clause of Art. 11(1) also makes it rather difficult to follow the Senate’s view that an authorisation of the type presumed by the Senate could be derived from the Treaty provisions. Art. 11(1) makes the carrying out of the Treaty provisions, including the implementation of obligations arising from the Treaty, subject to the parties’ respective constitutional processes. Thus, the objective and purpose of the Treaty and the measures to carry out its provisions must be constitutionally assessed independently of one another. Therefore, the Treaty’s objective cannot lend legitimating force to the constitutional assessment of implementing measures under the Treaty, as is claimed by the judgment ([…]). […]
204
The integration sought by and partially realised within NATO is based on two recommendations of the North Atlantic Council from 1950 and 1954 ([…]). In peacetime, SACEUR is only engaged in operational planning; they are not in command of the armed forces assigned to NATO, a command that can be revoked at any time by national decision. It is only in times of impending threat or at the latest from the start of hostilities that NATO command posts also assume operational command of the forces. This command only covers the operational area (G 3) of the four basic middle and high command areas, while other important areas such as logistics (G 4) are not integrated, even in times of impending threat ([…]). While these recommendations were available to the legislator, they were not the subject of the ratification procedure; nor was Section IV of the Final Act of the London conference, which is mentioned in the judgment ([…]), ratified by the legislator. For formal reasons alone, these aspects must not be part of the review of whether a law as required by Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law exists, no matter how great their significance for integration. This is decisive here.
205
3. The Court makes use of the legal concept of the ‘relatively open provisions’ of the North Atlantic Treaty ([…]). The ‘particular nature of the subject matter’ used as a standard demonstrates its dominance in its interpretation of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law: According to the Court, the subject matter [of the Treaty] is characterised by dynamic developments; it must be possible to take rapid and adaptable measures, which reflect ongoing changes in the allies’ political and strategic environment and the constant change in other security policy matters, such as the development of weapons technology ([…]). Only ‘open’
206
These provisions are programmatic statements regarding a process of integration ([…]), which, according to the Senate majority, is provided for in the North Atlantic Treaty. Yet even when these programmatic statements are openly worded, their nature is subject to change. They lack substantive specificity. In the Eurocontrol decision, a sufficient specificity of the process of integration provided for in the founding treaty was the prerequisite for transfer of the power in question without special legislative involvement. In the present judgment, this is replaced with far-reaching authorisations that the Senate rightly characterises as an authorisation framework ([…]). Thus, while the present judgment makes reference to the Eurocontrol decision, it departs from the fundamental tenets laid down in that decision.
207
This also applies to the nature of the transferred sovereign power. In its Eurocontrol decision, the Court justified its finding by expressly highlighting the narrow technical nature of the transferred power: it was a right to collect fees that complemented an equal right transferred by the Eurocontrol Convention (BVerfGE 58, 1 <38>). The power transferred in the present case, which authorises the use of missiles from German territory, is not comparable with the power transferred in the Eurocontrol decision.
208
The open nature of the provisions means that the Senate considers the fact that an integration agenda is possible under the treaties to be sufficient ([…]). This only confirms the lack of substantive specificity of the authorisation. Openly worded provisions can be used for different programmes. Today, they might concern consent to the deployment of Pershing II missiles, tomorrow, they could include consent to the deployment of neutron bombs, and at a later date grant the right to severe pre-emptive destruction on German territory by allied forces in order to halt advances by Warsaw Pact troops in the event of a state of defence. If everything that can be summarised under the terms ‘jointly developed strategy’ and, in the event of a state of defence, ‘jointly realisable strategy’ is considered to be covered by openly worded provisions, the counterpoint to the requirements of a process of integration, namely, the requirement of the strict interpretation of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law as specified in the first Eurocontrol decision, is abandoned. When the Senate majority is so receptive to the specific nature of the subject matter in applying Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law, the only remaining standard of review of a change to the agenda is ‘the fundamental objective of NATO as a defensive alliance, as laid down in the aforementioned treaties’ ([…]). The constitutional substance of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law has almost evaporated from the pressure of the imbalance between ends and means. It is not the Constitution, but only the purpose of the treaty that then determines how openly worded a provision may be in order to authorise the transfer of sovereign powers.
209
Consequently, in the view of the Senate majority, a change to the programme that is significant under constitutional law and would require a new law under Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law cannot be found to exist even assuming the applicant’s presumption that there is a new strategic dimension to the weapon systems in question and their deployment on German territory is correct ([…]). Instead, a change to the programme can only occur if the Federal Government, in giving its consent, intended to launch an attack. The broad leeway for the executive’s powers to make assessments and to act that this authorisation provides even leads the Senate to ask whether the legislator could impose special statutory obligations on the executive in light of Art. 20(2) of the Basic Law ([…]). This goes beyond the mere introduction of statutory authorisation frameworks for the executive within the scope of Art. 24 of the Basic Law, within which the executive may transfer German sovereign powers. This is because the Court invokes the principle of the separation of powers to call into question the legislator’s right to act in its own sphere and to make such an authorisation framework broader or narrower depending on its own assessment.
210
Before the first Eurocontrol decision was rendered, legal scholars assumed that the legislator itself must decide whether and to what extent sovereign powers are transferred ([…]). The first Eurocontrol decision loosened the link between the act approving the transfer of sovereign powers and the formal act of Parliament, albeit under narrow conditions. The present judgment sets in motion the erosion of the requirement of a statutory provision enshrined in Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law.
211
Other than the requirement of a statutory provision for changes to the existing division of territory into Länder, Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law contains the only requirement of a statutory provision in favour of the ordinary legislator which cannot be dispensed with even in cases of emergency (Art. 115e(2) of the Basic Law). In its judgment, the Senate replaces this requirement of a statutory provision with an authorising framework that is so openly worded that even the standards set by Art. 80(1) second sentence of the Basic Law for domestic authorising statutes are relinquished. This illustrates how the judgment tilts the constitutional framework in favour of the executive.
212
4. Even if one were to agree with the Senate majority that the openly worded provisions of the North Atlantic Treaty constitute an integration agenda and thus an authorising framework for the Federal Government, as set forth in the judgment, it would also be necessary, when determining the specific content of this agenda, to take into account the resolution of the allies affirmed in the preamble of the North Atlantic Treaty:
213
to safeguard the freedom, common heritage and civilisation of their peoples, founded on the principles of democracy, individual liberty and the rule of law.
214
This common ground forms the basis for the commitment to a joint organisation of defence, which was only affirmed following this text and used by the Senate to support its view. This means, however, that the new strategic dimension asserted by the applicant, which the Senate deemed to be irrelevant for constitutional review, then gains constitutional relevance. This is because the cited objective must be included in the defensive purpose of the NATO pact, which the Senate considers to be decisive. With Germany’s accession into this pact, this objective also extends to the German people and must therefore be achievable by Germany in military conflict, meaning the Federal Republic of Germany must not be only the main field of battle from a military perspective. Politically speaking, Germany must remain both the subject and the object of joint defence endeavours.
215
The legislator that adopted the 1955 acts of approval was aware of the geo-strategic situation of a divided Germany, including the serious consequences in the event of a state of defence arising therefrom. But precisely because of our inescapable geo-strategic situation, the acts of approval cannot be taken to mean that they are a de facto authorisation for the government to pursue any integration endeavour, regardless of whether such an endeavour increases the possibility or even likelihood of war and thus a threat to the existence of the German people.
216
It is not for the Federal Constitutional Court to decide on the deployment of the missiles. However, the risks of such deployment would have needed to be assessed by the Senate – either as submitted by the applications or in an ex officio investigation by the Court – to determine whether the grounds for an increased risk of war were only minimal, and therefore negligible, i.e., whether this is a residual risk within the meaning of the Kalkar decision (cf. BVerfGE 49, 89 <137 f., 141 ff.>), or whether the grounds are of such weight that this must be considered a serious possibility of an increased risk of war. In the latter case, this would amount to a change to the integration agenda – in the wording of the first Eurocontrol decision, an extension (BVerfGE 58, 1 <38>) – which would no longer be covered by the authorisation framework and would result in the legislator having to decide whether to give its consent.
217
[…]
218-220
a) […]
221
b) […]
222
c) If the review had provided one or more indications that the greater protection sought by modern weapons would also entail a serious increase in the risk of war, consent to this decision from the legislator would have been required.
223
5. If it is recognised that the task of legislation is inextricably linked with Parliament, and that the principle of the separation of powers precludes the conferral of this task on other organs, executive organs in particular ([…]), the Senate’s view regarding the requirement of a law in Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law cannot be justified by the assertion that there was a need, let alone the necessity, to ease the burden on the legislator that might arise from having to adopt legislation in rapidly and constantly changing situations. Developments in strategic doctrine and weapons technology are not determined by short-term circumstances, but instead are long-term in nature. […] Thus, it was not – in the words of the judgment – part of the ‘particular nature of the subject matter’ of common defence of the allies to presume constant change in the political and strategic environment or in the development of weapons technology and weaponry, which would have required immediate action.
224
6. The Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces is also not a sufficient ‘law’ within the meaning of Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law.
225
It is true that Art. 1 of the Convention also contains an authorisation to improve armament. […]
226
However, this armament does not include every instrument of modern weapons technology. Pershing II missiles, whose speed enables them to be used against so-called time-urgent targets, are particularly unnecessary for the armed forces and their armament, since, according to modern strategic thinking, they are intended for paralysis strikes against the aforementioned command, control and communication structures in the far-flung hinterland of the Warsaw Pact. Such novel types of weapons are not a modernisation of the weapons of the armed forces, they are altogether outside the scope of the treaties. Another way of looking at it would be to understand Art. 1 as a blanket authorisation for the use of any type of weapon on German territory that could be used for defence as a military or political instrument of the United States or its partners against the Soviet Union and the Warsaw Pact states, regardless of the political consequences that might arise from its deployment in the Federal Republic of Germany – the state closest to those states, and the one which would be most affected in the event of war. The inexorable and, at the same time, unpredictable progress in weapons technology and weaponry is no justification for taking away the control over the sovereignty of the state from the legislator, and transferring it to the Federal Government under Art. 24(1) of the Basic Law as if it were fate. In this respect, too, it must be noted that in interpreting an international treaty governing the political relations of the Federation, the political starting point of the treaty is of particular significance (cf. BVerfGE 4, 157 <168 and headnote no. 3>).
227
Moreover, the Federal Government’s express statement that the German Bundestag will have the opportunity of adopting a position within the framework of its parliamentary oversight powers, as it did in the past, before their deployment on German territory shows that these weapons are not part of the traditional notion of weapon modernisation under Art. 1 of the Convention on the Presence of Foreign Forces (BTDrucks. 10/487, p. 6 f.; highlighted for the purposes of this opinion). […]
III.
228
According to Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law, treaties governing the political relations of the Federation or relating to subjects of legislation require the consent or participation, in the form of a federal law, of the bodies responsible in such a case for the enactment of federal legislation. The Senate holds that this provision of the Basic Law is not applicable to the challenged declaration of consent regarding the deployment and the transfer of sovereign powers on the grounds that it is a unilateral declaration. I do not agree with this assessment.
229
1. It is doubtful whether the Federal Government’s consent is not part of an international treaty after all ([…]). This need not be decided here, however.
230
2. According to the Senate, the requirement of a parliamentary decision in Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law has the purpose of preventing permanent or indissoluble binding effects under international law without the consent of the Bundestag ([…]). This statement should have prompted the Senate to examine whether the declaration of consent, if it did not require a law because it was unilateral, could even be made by the Federal Government in a form other than as part of a treaty. The purpose of Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law would be defeated if the executive could determine whether the requirement of a law applied through the choice of the legal form of its declarations. Consent cannot be categorised as a typical unilateral constitutive declaration under international law because, as consent, it presupposes something that already exists conceptually and also has legal significance. This renders the objection that the consequence of this idea is that the Federal Government is prevented from making domestically effective unilateral declarations under international law invalid.
231
3. If consent as a unilateral act under international law is to be possible under constitutional law, the function of Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law requires the extension of the requirement of a law to such acts.
232
According to the Senate majority, the separation of powers precludes such an extension. It would amount to a ‘concentration of political power’, an ‘encroachment on central decision-making powers of the executive’ ([…]) and would run counter to the system of distribution of power, responsibility and oversight provided for in the Basic Law.
233
If, on the other hand, the Senate reviews the specific sphere of involvement of the legislator under Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law ([…]), it comes to different conclusions: The legislator pursuant to Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law is – so far as the Senate’s considerations must be understood to mean – not at all capable of challenging the executive’s control over foreign policy matters. This can therefore be no question of an encroachment on the central decision-making powers of the executive. The legal scholarship, conversely, speaks of the risk of ‘gradual erosion’ of the legislator’s participation rights under Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law ([…]).
234
The interpretive method used by the Senate with regard to the interpretation of the principle of the separation of powers is questionable. The importance of methodology is demonstrated by the Senate’s consideration that political risks arising from the Basic Law’s division of competences must be accepted under constitutional law. The Senate interprets Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law in light of Art. 20(2) of the Basic Law ([…]), without first interpreting Art. 20(2) of the Basic Law in light of Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law. Art. 59(2) is an express reflection of the principle of the separation of powers enshrined in the Basic Law. The scope of this principle therefore cannot be determined by an idealised scheme of the separation of powers. The decisive criterion for interpreting Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law […] is its function. At least with regard to fundamental rights, the Court has regularly defined the requirement of a law on the basis of the protection that this requirement serves to ensure for the individual.
235
With regard to the requirement of a law in Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law, insofar as it concerns matters of legislation, the function of this provision mandates that there be no gap between the obligation under international law and the domestic right to also extend the requirement of a law to unilateral acts.
236
In determining the scope of the element of regulating political relations, which is relevant here, the function of Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law is again decisive. In its judgment of 31 July 1973 on the Basic Treaty (BVerfGE 36, 1), the Court emphasised the aspect of political oversight as decisive for the inclusion of a treaty with a state that is part of Germany ([…]) within the concept of the term ‘treaty’, which generally refers to treaties with other states (cf. Art. 59(1) of the Basic Law) ([…]). If such inclusion is required by the aspect of political oversight, the same must apply if an act is part of foreign affairs, even if it constitutes a unilateral act concerning political relations rather than a treaty.
237
According to the Senate’s decision of 8 August 1978 (BVerfGE 49, 89 <126 f.>), Art. 59(2) first sentence of the Basic Law is a specific manifestation of the Basic Law’s general requirement of a law ‘encompassing all essential decisions’. If the Federal Government’s consent regarding the stationing of forces is such an essential foreign policy decision that it requires political oversight of the legislator, then it too is also subject to the requirement of a law.
238
[…]
239
The Senate points to the Bundestag’s oversight powers, in particular its power to elect the Chancellor, as a counterbalance. The election of a new Chancellor, however, does not render the government’s act invalid under international law, nor does it give effect to the participation rights of the Bundesrat. Above all, neither the parliamentary form of government provided for by the Basic Law nor experience with this Constitution suggests that the relationship between the two political powers should be understood to mean that the election of a new Chancellor should be the response to individual government measures. Political oversight is to be exercised within a stable governmental framework. The Constitution allows for a combination of stable government with an extension of parliamentary competence beyond that provided by the Weimar Constitution. The combination of both powers was further developed after the Basic Law entered into force, with an increasing detachment from the ‘separation of powers monism’ of the previous constitutional era (cf. Arts. 45a, 45b, 45c, 87a(1), 115a(1), 115a(2) in conjunction with Art. 53a of the Basic Law).
240
4. Art. 59(2) of the Basic Law must be applied to the declaration of consent.
241
Firstly, the consent transfers a sovereign right to the United States that can be exercised by the US President. With this sovereign right, the President can, even if the exercise is within the limits set by the North Atlantic Treaty, involve the Federal Republic of Germany in a war that could threaten the existence of both German states.
242
Secondly, the consent required a law because it ruled out a political solution to the security problem concerning medium-range missiles, i.e. negotiations, for the foreseeable future.
243
As the Soviet Union let the United States know that it would not continue negotiations if medium-range missiles were stationed, and the Federal Republic of Germany is the only country in which Pershing II missiles were to be stationed and are in fact stationed, the Federal Republic of Germany was in the unique situation of being able to influence the chance to continue the Geneva INF negotiations. For the Federal Republic of Germany in particular, the possible political solution these negotiations represented was a serious alternative to a weapons-based security solution such as the deployment of missiles, because the latter can only provide security in the short term given advancement in weapons technology on both sides. The end of negotiations was not just a secondary consequence of the declaration of consent (cf. in this regard BVerfGE 1, 372 <382>), but was part of that decision, given that consent to the deployment of the missiles ruled out the alternative of a negotiated solution for the time being.
- Mahrenholz